I put together this list more than a month ago, when
perpetua54 advertised at
academics_anon. Then I sat on it for awhile, until the early semester crazy faded and I now am just a bit more available to parry your challenges, quench your queries, and prostrate my intellect for your procrastinatory amusement. So have at it!
(
a list )
First, a warm-up. Is this on your list just because it's generally important, or is there a more particular reason you've chosen it? Because, with the Grice and the Nagel up there, I'd think "Two Dogmas" or especially "Web of Belief" would fit more closely.
Reply
I picked this over "Two Dogmas" mainly for quasi-stylistic reasons. For one, I think the writing in "On What There Is" is just exemplary. More importantly, though, I enjoy how Quine sets up the dialectic and moves through some incredibly complex material really effectively for just a single piece. "Two Dogmas" is less clear in some crucial places.
Really, though, this article is just a placeholder for Quine's view as a whole - that's what I really appreciate. But I do think that "On What There Is" is the best statement of it (that I've read at any rate).
I should mention, though, that I don't specialize in metaphysics, epistemology, or the philosophy of language. So my appreciation is decidedly of the only-partly-informed variety!
Reply
Reply
Grice I use much more explicitly - I think many of our purported intuitions about test cases (in, among other domains, ethics and the philosophy of mind) are best explained by pragmatic facts of assertoric context. I believe this is compatible with recognizing that, when pragmatics aren't the full answer, a Quinean approach can help explain what we actually are doing in making theoretical claims.
Reply
Can you give me a ferinstance here? And please, please tell me that the bit at the end doesn't mean you think Dennett's "strategy" works for getting rid of qualia.
Reply
Oddly, the best example I can think of is from neither ethics nor phil mind, but from metaphysics. David Lewis, somewhat infamously, offers an analysis of causation as counterfactual dependence (or, in his last version, counterfactual influence). Speaking loosely, A causes B just in case B would not have happened (or would have happened in a different way) had A not happened (or happened in a different way).
Now, this seems to entail lots of crazy stuff. For instance, it entails that my birth causes my death; had I not been born, I could not die. Lewis responds to the objection by suggesting that these crazy entailments are indeed correct (my birth does cause my death!) - but it makes no pragmatic sense to ever assert them, and so that's why we feel queasy about them ( ... )
Reply
I will have more questions later, but now, it is time for whiskey.
Reply
Have whiskey fun!
Reply
What I meant to ask was: "I don't really work in this area and probably never will. But is their work cool enough that I should read it anyway?"
Reply
Now then, on to more questions. How do you feel about the Grice in light of, for example, Lewis's "Scorekeeping"?
Reply
Unfortunately, I haven't read any of this in at least five years, and the detailed differences among the various linguistic pragmatists are fuzzy in my mind. I have this vague notion that Lewis is building upon - not necessarily contradicting - what Grice said, but I could be wrong.
Reply
Reply
Reply
Reply
It seems kind of crazy- unless he thinks that all bets are off once people start cooperating, so in that case there's no point in trying to capture those interactions systematically.
But the Lewisian approach then does look comparably better.
Reply
Reply
Leave a comment